Many economic choices involve tradeoffs over time.
Simple example: learning a new instrument.
Key economic examples: savings/investment, education, health.
Four stages in the theory of intertemporal choice:
Then \begin{equation*} U = 100 + 0.9\cdot 100 + 0.9^2\cdot 100 + 0.9^3\cdot 100\; + ... \end{equation*}
Or \begin{equation*} U = 100 + 90 + 81 + 72.9\; + ... \end{equation*}
The action a person thinks they should take in the future always coincides with the action that they actually prefer once the time comes.
Examples:
Their consumption utility for marshmallows in each period is:
u(no marshmallows) | = | 0 |
u(1 marshmallow) | = | 20 |
u(2 marshmallows) | = | 30 |
u(no marshmallows) | = | 0 |
u(1 marshmallow) | = | 20 |
u(2 marshmallows) | = | 30 |
Let $\delta = 0.9$. Then:
For "reasonable" discount rates, child will prefer to wait for two marshmallows.
Their consumption utility for marshmallows in each period is:
u(no marshmallows) | = | 0 |
u(1 marshmallow) | = | 20 |
u(2 marshmallows) | = | 30 |
u(no marshmallows) | = | 0 |
u(1 marshmallow) | = | 20 |
u(2 marshmallows) | = | 30 |
Let $\delta = 0.9$. Then:
Despite the immediate temptation, the child will still prefer to wait for two marshmallows.
Dynamic consistency implies:
Samuelson: his functional form was arbitrary.
"It is completely arbitrary to assume that the individual behaves so as to maximize an integral of the form envisaged."- Samuelson (1937) A Note on Measurement of Utility
In some sense, dynamic consistency was a revolution.
"Suppose I could give you:
- 100 in cash right now, or
- X in cash in two weeks.
What is the smallest amount of money, X, I could offer you in two weeks to make you forgo the 100 right now?"
$\overline{X}=164$
Consumption of various forms follows the pay cycle.
That is, people buy steaks, cigarettes, and alcohol on their payday, and struggle to coast through the end of the month.
On average...
If applied to an additional two weeks:
100 now $\sim\frac{164}{100}\cdot 164\approx 269$ in four weeks.If applied to a year delay:
100 now $\sim\left(\frac{164}{100}\right)^{26}\cdot 100\approx 38.5$M in a year.If applied to a two year delay:
100 now $\sim\left(\frac{164}{100}\right)^{52}\cdot 100\approx 1.5$T in two years.100 today $\sim$ 101 tomorrow
If applied to the next day:
100 now $\sim\frac{101}{100}\cdot 101=102.01$ in two days.If applied recursively for a year:
100 now $\sim\left(\frac{101}{100}\right)^{365}\cdot 100\approx 617,487$ in a year.If applied to a two year delay:
Indifferent between 100 now and 1T in two years.Also means indifferent between
"Suppose I could give you:
- 100 in cash in eight weeks, or
- X in cash in ten weeks.
What is the smallest amount of money, X, I could offer you in ten weeks to make you forgo the 100 in eight weeks?"
$\overline{X}=122$
"What $x$ makes you indifferent between $y$ today and $x$ in $z$ time?" $\rightarrow\delta$.
$y$ | $z$ | Median $x$ | Discount factor $\delta$ |
15 | 1 month | 20 | 0.032 |
15 | 10 years | 100 | 0.83 |
40 | 6 months | 50 | 0.64 |
40 | 4 years | 90 | 0.82 |
The discount factor is increasing in the time delay, indicating subjects were more patient in the long run.
Back to Frederick, Loewenstein and O'Donoghue (2002)
In the real world...behavior is not consistent with exponential discounting, which claims the discount rate is always the same.
Ulysses and the Sirens:
"These nymphs had the power...of charming by their song all who heard them, so that mariners were impelled to cast themselves into the sea to destruction. Circe directed Ulysses to stop the ears of his sailors with wax, so that they should not hear the strain; to have himself bound to the mast, and to enjoin his people, whatever he might say or do, by no means to release him till they should have passed the Sirens' island."
Financial advice:
"Cut up your credit and store cards! If possible get rid of all of your credit cards...Put temptation out of reach. If you really can't do without a credit card, limit yourself to only one. Put it in a tub of water and stick it in the freezer. Extreme? Maybe, but it will make you think hard about any impulse purchases you make in the future while you are standing there waiting for it to defrost."
Anonymous teacher evaluation:
"The problem sets should have been graded. I had no incentive to do them, and as a result did poorly on the exams."
Let's modify utility to take into account:
Start with exponential discounting:
\begin{equation*} u_t + \delta u_{t+1} + \delta^2 u_{t+2} + \delta^3 u_{t+3} + ... \end{equation*}But add a short-term discount factor $\beta < 1$.
\begin{equation*} u_t + \beta\left[\delta u_{t+1} + \delta^2 u_{t+2} + \delta^3 u_{t+3} + ...\right] \end{equation*}Example: suppose $\beta=\frac{1}{2}$ and $\delta=0.9$.
One marshmallow at $t=1$...or two at $t=2$?
u(no marshmallows) | = | 0 |
u(1 marshmallow) | = | 20 |
u(2 marshmallows) | = | 30 |
Decision at $t=0$: Waits for 2!
Example: suppose $\beta=\frac{1}{2}$ and $\delta=0.9$.
One marshmallow at $t=1$...or two at $t=2$?
u(no marshmallows) | = | 0 |
u(1 marshmallow) | = | 20 |
u(2 marshmallows) | = | 30 |
Decision at $t=1$: Take 1 now!
Dates: | $t = 0$ | $t = 1$ | $t = 2$ |
Utility: | $u_0=-1$ | $u_1=-\frac{3}{2}$ | $u_2=-\frac{5}{2}$ |
Assume: | $\beta=\frac{1}{2}$ | and | $\delta=1$ |
What will this student elect to do at time $t=0$?
Utility of completing the problem set on $t=0$: $-1$
Utility of completing the problem set on $t=1$: $-\frac{3}{4}$
Utility of completing the problem set on $t=2$: $-\frac{5}{4}$
"I'll do it tomorrow night..."
Dates: | $t = 0$ | $t = 1$ | $t = 2$ |
Utility: | $u_0=-1$ | $u_1=-\frac{3}{2}$ | $u_2=-\frac{5}{2}$ |
Assume: | $\beta=\frac{1}{2}$ | and | $\delta=1$ |
What will this student elect to do at time $t=1$?
Utility of completing the problem set on $t=1$: $-\frac{3}{2}$
Utility of completing the problem set on $t=2$: $-\frac{5}{4}$
"I'll do it tomorrow night..."